Is there really information being conveyed within a cell?

Sure. I just don’t see what the problem is here. I’m talking to someone about the genetic code, and in describing the translation system they state that the set of tRNA molecule can be considered to function as an interpreter between mRNA codons and amino acid sequence, for example. What is the error that is likely to occur here? I don’t think anyone in their right mind, who already knows what molecules are, is going to think you’re positing a tiny little molecular man employed to do interpretations (or whatever the heck). And if they don’t already know what molecules are, that is their actual problem, not that we are applying the concept of an interpreter to tRNA.

I just don’t see that something has been stretched beyond any breaking point. I think you’re inventing a problem where there actually is none.

1 Like

Today, there are numerous software solutions and apps for computers and smartphones that can decode Morse code in real-time. They use advanced signal processing to filter out noise and accurately interpret Morse code from various sources, including historical recordings or live radio signals. These solutions operate through purely natural laws. And yet, the Morse code is a semiotic code. The same thing is true for the genetic code. The fact that it operates through chemistry doesn’t mean that it is not a genuine semiotic code.

Even if we stipulate that to be true, your argument doesn’t work as it’s premises are known to be either false or simply beg the question.

2 Likes

OK, so it may be possible to define “semiosis” in such a way that eliminates any entailment that an intelligent being is involved.

That pretty much kills your argument dead, right?

3 Likes

The issue here is not the probably impossible task to demonstrate that 1) a non-natural cause exists and that 2) it is the source of the genetic code. Rather, as you alluded to at 260, it is whether these two assertions are grounded on reason. The Kalam or the fine tuning arguments are reasonable arguments in support of the first assertion. As for the second assertion, I have put forward a reasonable syllogism in support of it at 260. Note that the reasonable character of assertion 1 give stronger ground for the reasonable character of assertion 2. To sum up, although ID proponents cannot demonstrate the two assertions, they can advance good reasons to support them.

Please describe the criteria you use to decide whether a claim is “reasonable.”

3 Likes

Only in so far as it couldn’t have a probability greater than 0 if it didn’t exist, of course. So if we stipulate that some sort of supernatural entity with at least the ability to create the genetic code exists, that would raise the probability that it did so, at least above zero. But that alone tells us nothing about how much greater than zero. “Stronger ground” here could be anything between infinitely close to 0, and infinitely close to 100%. This is completely uninformative.

But there’s no reason to think a supernatural entity was involved in the origin of the genetic code, and all the data we have on the early evolution of life indicates that the genetic code and the translation system is the product of evolution in some sort of RNA world. There’s no support for the hypothesis that the supernatural was involved, and it’s completely unnecessary to explain what we see.

2 Likes

And why would anyone care if it were? As has been pointed out to you by me and by others, these purely verbal, purely argumentative paths don’t get you to any useful place. How we describe something doesn’t change what it is. And there is nothing at all about the nature of the genetic codes which supports any claim of design.

It actually very much is. You are not engaged in a discussion of a question that can be answered by any means other than the empirical. If you do indeed think that demonstration of those propositions is impossible, I think that’s correct; but once you reach that conclusion there is no need to discuss the matter any further as nothing worthwhile can possibly be achieved.

I would hate to have my posts construed in that way. That a proposition is grounded in reason is simply never enough, when the question is a clear and frank question of fact.

Not really.

No, you haven’t. Seriously, now. Speak seriously for a change.

If they could, they would have. Hasn’t happened yet.

3 Likes

They’re not – they’re “grounded” in a number of fallacious Hasty Generalisations.

Let me demonstrate:

  1. A landau is a type of horse-drawn carriage.

  2. This is also a landau:

  1. But this is not a horse-drawn carriage.

Words get extended to cover new concepts. Conclusions that might be valid about older usages do not necessarilly apply to newer usages of a word.

You have not demonstrated that the premise “a code requires a coder” applies to genetic code.

Neither are considered “reasonable arguments” by anybody other than Christian Apologists.

3 Likes

They could, however, advance ID hypotheses that make empirical predictions, but they never do. Why?

5 Likes

No, the data we have don’t indicate such things. You are guilty of wishful speculations here.

I mean, to me this is just another instance of a ‘Watchmaker analogy’ and I find it rather uninteresting. Even putting aside the fact that the ‘genetic code’ is more like a cypher than an actual code, the question on whether or not the analogy holds does not really help our understanding, sometimes it can distract us.

It reminds me of when physicists were first trying to understand the structure of the atom, trying to figure out how the negatively charged electrons did not crash into the positively charged nucleus. Some compared it to how planets were also able to avoid colliding with the sun by remaining in a stable ‘oribit’. Hence why we are still talking about ‘electron orbitals’. Of course, electrons are not planets, and one can debate whether the analogy holds or not. Regardless whether you want to keep the analogy (and we often do as a conceptual stepping-stone in high school) that doesn’t matter to the questions of how electrons actually behave. Similarly, we can also argue endlessly whether the genetic code is really a cypher or not, it tells us little about system in question and I would like to move away from such analogies (or at least not put so much stock into it) for the same reasons outlined by Daniel Nicholson in his papers where he criticize the many metaphors that compare organisms to machines. Also see this discussion I had on the Forum.

Case in point, one can argue over (1) whether tRNA’s is really ‘interpreting’ anything. Doesn’t the anti-codon just bind onto its complementary codons due to the physics of hydrogen bonding? (2) Why do we assign this ‘interpreter’ role to the tRNA. Can’t we just as easily say that the codon ‘interprets’ the tRNA? (3) How is ‘interpretation’ even defined? Does the action have to be cognitive, e.g. when I am interpreting a red-coded faucet as one that provides hot water? If so, then aren’t we treating tRNA as if they are tiny homunculi inside the cell? If cognitive agency is not required, then can one say that oxygen and hydrogen are ‘interpreting’ each other to produce H2O? If not, why not?

When the genetic code was first described, it was indeed said that there was no stereochemical relationship between the (anti-)codons and the amino acids even by prominent biologists like Francis Crick and Jacques Monod. This led to the hypothesis that the genetic code is a frozen accident; i.e. the code we ended up with was just one of many equally likely possibilities, but the biosphere ended up being stuck with one code. However, this is very wrong in my opinion. The genetic code(s) has a lot of non-arbitrary structure and in more ways than one.

First, we are all familiar with the fact it is ‘degenerate’ (redundant), since there are (4x4x4=) 64 different codons that code for 20 (rarely 22) amino acids. If we would randomly assign each codon to one amino acid, the random genetic code we would end up with would (by overwhelming probability) have redundancy equally distributed in the 3 nucleotide of the codons. However, this is definitely NOT true for the genetic code(s) that we observe. Most of the redundancy is concentrated in the 3rd nucleotide P3. For example, if P2 is C, or if P1+P2 are G or C and G or U respectively, then P3 is completely redundant; changing the nucleotide at P3 won’t change the amino acid. When the P3 does matter, the only distinction that matters is purine (AG) vs pyrimidine (UC) but there are two interesting exceptions: the start codon AUG (Methionine) vs AU[U/C/A] (Isoleucine) and UGG (Tryptophan) vs UGA (‘Opal’ stop codon). And regarding non-standard genetic codes; organelles and some organisms use UGA to also specify Tryptophan, while some other organisms use UGA for Glycine or for selenocysteine (one of the 2 non-standard amino acids). In contrast, although P1 is never redundant in the strict sense, changing the nucleotides at P1 does occasionally result in the same specified amino aicid: CG[N] vs AG[A/G] for Arginine and CU[N] vs UU[A/G] for Leucine. However, changing the nucleotide at P2 will ALWAYS result in a different amino acid specified.


So the P1, P2, P3 positions are clearly not arbitrary with regard to redundancy;… but why? First, is the geometry of the tRNA loop allows some free movement of the first nucleotide of the anti-codon (opposite to the P3 of the codon). This free movement allows the nucleotide to pair up in a manner that does not follow Watson-Crick rules, called wobble base pairs. For example, if the P1 of the anti-codon is G, then it can pair with C (Watson-Crick) or U (wobble base pair) in the mRNA. Note that in this example, C and U are both pyrimidines. Indeed, when anti-codon P1 is a purine it still prefers to bind with pyrimidines and vice versa. Hence why when codon P3 matters, it’s distinct that most often matters is purine (AG) vs pyrimidine (UC). Thus, one anti-codon is able to bind onto multiple codons, hence organisms don’t make 61 tRNAs, one for each unique non-stop codon (most make fewer than 45).

But why does doesn’t P3 matter when P2 is C, or when P1+P2 are G/C+G/U? Well, the geometry of the tRNA makes P2 the most reliable to form canonical Watson-Crick base pairs. P1 is a little less reliable but still far more reliable than the wobble-prone P3. Furthermore, not every base pair is equal; G-C have 3 hydrogen bonds while U-A have only 2. Thus, G-C base pairs are stronger than A-U. Secondly, due to the geometric differences between the codon and anti-codon, the direction of the bond also matters. Pyrimidine(codon)-purine(anti-codon) are stronger than purine(codon)-pyrimidine(anti-codon), e.g. U-A pairs are stronger when U is in the codon and G-C pairs are stronger when the C is in the codon. So, when only looking at the codon, the order of bases that form strongest to weakest is C>G>U>A. This is why P3 is always redundant when P2 is C, i.e. when the most reliable position [P2] has the strongest binding possible [C in the codon]; and why P3 is still redundant when P1+P2 are G/C+G/U, i.e. when P1 has the strongest or 2nd strongest base [C or G] and P2 has the 2nd or 3rd strongest base [G or U]. Base ‘A’ is the weakest, which explains why P3 is never redundant when P2 is ‘A’. We also see interesting things with regard to the start codon and stop codons. The wobble position for the start codon is at the P1 (AUG, and lesser used CUG > GUG > UUG), because the start-tRNA interacts with the P-site (for initiation) of the ribosome while all other tRNAs interact with the A-site (for elongation). The geometry is almost reversed between the A and P sites. The stop codons (UAA>UGA>UAG in order of usage) are rather weak with very few hydrogen bonds. Perhaps they are too weak to be used for codon/anti-codon interaction, serving better as recognition sites for protein terminating factors. And when these and similar codons are used for specifyiing amino acids, they are used for rather special and rarely used amino acids; e.g. Tryptophan and especially Selenocysteine.

Aside from the redundancy, there are also non-arbitrary relationships between the codons and the properties of the amino acids themselves. This becomes more clear when we change the wheel graph of the genetic code such that we can use P2 to group the amino-acids into four quadrants. Here we we see that the amino acids within each group share the same properties regarding their ‘polarity’ and thus their affinity to water. Codons with P2 as U specify amino acids that are hydrophobic; those with A specify ones that are hydrophilic, and those with G/G specify ones that are semi-polar. The only exception is Arginine (Arg) an hydrophilic amino acid in the otherwise semipolar ‘G’ group. Polarity is among the most important properties to since protein folding involves a 'hydrophobic collapse’. You also have other important amino acid properties: strongly acidic vs strongly basic and aliphatic vs aromatic. Amino acids that share such properties are specified by codons that often only differ by one base.

Why is this the case? Again, this is likely due to P2 being the most reliable for reasons explained previously. Assigning amino acids with different properties to the different “codon groups” which are more easily distinguished by the translation system means that most translational errors occur within the codon groups, meaning when an amino-acid is misplaced it tends to have similar properties to the one it replaced; and such amino acid substitutions are often tolerated. Case in point, almost no sarcomere (unit of muscle) in your body will be error-free regarding the amino acid sequences of its proteins, yet you are still able to walk.

But we can go even further. The nucleotides of the codons don’t only correspond to the properties of the amino acids. The codons also have a non-arbitrary correspondence to the biochemical synthesis of the amino acids. Also see section 6.1 of this excellent paper, particularly figure 6, which is TOO big to put here. A less comprehensive but simpler one is shown below. As you can see, the P1 of the codon correlates to the alpha-keto acid precursor of the amino acid: C (ketoglutarate) A (oxaloacetate) and U (Pyruvate). Furthermore, other nucleotides correlate with the subsequent chemical reactions. For example, if P1 = G, start with α-ketoacids and P2 correlates to the subsequent chemical alteration(s).

Exactly why this metabolic correspondence exists in the genetic code is the case is up for debate. In this paper the authors propose that specifically dinucleotides (the precursor to the first two bases of codons) were responsible for catalyzing the synthesis of amino acids from α-ketoacids, and that the sequence of the dinucleotide chemically determined the specific amino acid synthesized. I am not sure about this myself.

When I see this metabolic correspondence, it reminds me more about when amino-acids are charged to the tRNA they are still able to undergo chemistry which can change the amino acid into a different one. It’s one type of error that can occur during translation. Many amino acids are ‘connected’ within the same biochemical pathway. One example, glutamate-tRNA is able to change glutamine-tRNA. In fact, this is happens in all Archaea and most bacteria, where one aaRS enzyme (GluRS) charges glutamate onto two types of tRNA, but when one type is charged, the glutamate (while attached to the tRNA) is changed into glutamine by an amidotransferase. Some bacteria and all eukaryotes do have a seperate aaRS (GlnRS) for directly charging glutamine, but evolved from the aforementioned aaRS (GluRS) via gene duplication and neofunctionalisation. This is one likely mechanism for how new amino acids were incorporated into the genetic code.

6 Likes

Your evidence for this is …?

That you are not aware, or that the experiments are not being done, is not evidence.

When I said “we don’t see”, I’m saying that we don’t see nucleotides, etc being formed in nature.

Can we do things in the lab? Of course. It’s a form of chemical engineering.

How do you know:

  1. What is necessary for life to begin?
  2. That natural processes don’t account for it?

You seem to possess knowledge not held by any scientist currently working in origin of life research. You should contact them and tell them why you think they’re wasting their time.

If the natural processes that led lead to the origin of life exist, then we could observe them. We wouldn’t have to try and recreate something that supposedly happened in the past.

No known way, but could there be an unknown way?

In any case, maybe life did not begin with DNA being expressed into proteins and ribozymes. Is that possible?

We can always speculate.

Functional information, whether strings of bits or nucleotides, can be processed by something else to produce an effect. The something can be an intelligent mind, or a device capable of processing the information.

The words in this post are held in memory as a functional string of bits. A digital photo is a functional string of bits. The sequence of bases that can be expressed into a functional protein or transcribed into a functional rna is a functional string of nucleotides. And so on.

The premise is that a random string of bits (or nucleotides) won’t be functional and that it takes an intelligent mind (or devices produced by an intelligent mind) to produce such a functional string.

Not really because, as you have admitted, we have countless examples of phenomena that can be accounted for thru naturalism. So there is no need to look for gaps where naturalistic explanations might be hiding. We already know they exist.

I’ve made no such admission. Saying that something works by natural processes (chemistry, physics, etc) is not the same thing as saying that naturalism (only natural things exist) is true.

“God of the gaps”, OTOH, often refers to the situation in which an unanswered question is used as evidence for the existence of a god, on the assumption that only the existence of a god could serve as the answer. It is very sloppy thinking.

“God of the gaps” deals with unanswered questions about observable natural phenomena. For example, “how does gravity really work?”.

I believe we are still waiting for you to provide a rigorous model that is used to characterize and measure “functional information.”

My comments on functional information don’t depend on being able to measure it, nor have I said that it can be done.

The RNA world hypothesis is supported by numerous different observations, not just that RNA can act as a catalyst and also store information. The fact that RNA either performs or can perform all the critical functions in translation, in addition to serving as an information storage system like it does in RNA viruses (and transiently following transcription from RNA), are just some of these observations.

That nucleotide and nucleobase-derived compounds are frequently used as cofactors in central metabolic reactions (are used as critical “helper” molecules that participate in catalysis by protein enzymes) is thought to be another remnant of the RNA world, and then there’s the fact that RNA monomers are actually chemical precursors of DNA monomers. Basically when cells biosynthesize DNA from the bottom up, they first make RNA and then further modify it into DNA, implying that the pathways for DNA synthesis are later elaborations on the pathways that made RNA first.

The fact that ribosomes are transcribed from DNA doesn’t mean it isn’t evidence for the RNA world hypothesis.

You seem to confuse evidence with proof. That the ribosome is a ribozyme doesn’t prove the RNA world hypothesis, but it’s central roles in translation (not just that peptidyl transferase is a ribozyme) are best explained as byproducts of an earlier stage in life’s evolution where RNA served much more central roles in replication and catalysis.

None of this is evidence for RNA World because RNA World supposedly happened before DNA and proteins existed.

Simply showing that rna has functionality in today’s “DNA World” (no argument about that) isn’t evidence that the same functionality occurred before DNA World began.

Are you suggesting that recreating something in the lab doesn’t count as “observing” it?

1 Like

Already went over this:

TL;DR The claim is not ‘RNA is functional, therefore RNA world’. The claim is that since RNA plays very specific roles that are at the center in biology (arguably even more central than what DNA does today) which prompted scientists to propose that RNA preceded DNA as an answer to the age old chicken-egg question. AND this predicted the catalytic properties of RNA that were discovered later, which has made the RNA world hypothesis more plausible.

8 Likes

All of it is. Your statement makes no sense.

More importantly, your creation hypothesis has made two falsified empirical predictions, which you falsely presented as facts because your approach is shallow and entirely rhetorical, based on a complete lack of understanding of catalysis.

Yet you haven’t addressed these two objectively falsified predictions, continuing your Gish Galloping.

Why to you appear to be afraid to go deeper and learn anything beyond creationist rhetoric?

2 Likes